Skip to main content

Pragmatic trials can address diagnostic controversies: recent lessons from gestational diabetes

Abstract

Objective

The aim of the paper is to discuss how a pragmatic definition could change our conception of diagnosis, using gestational diabetes mellitus (GDM) as an example.

Study design

We review the diagnostic controversy that followed an observational study showing a linear relationship between maternal glycaemia and adverse pregnancy outcomes and the resolution proposed 15 years later by a recent pragmatic trial comparing two screening approaches (one- vs two-step) with different diagnostic thresholds.

Results

The pragmatic trial involved approximately 24,000 women. The one-step screening strategy using lower GDM thresholds diagnosed twice as many women with GDM, but pregnancy outcomes were not different. We examine how the pragmatic approach integrates research into practice and defines the meaning of a diagnosis according to patient outcomes. The approach is ethically and scientifically sound as compared to the previous methodology, where observational research separated from care gave a theoretical definition of GDM that may have misled medical practice for two decades.

Conclusion

Pragmatic research integrated into practice can revolutionize our conception of medical diagnosis in the best medical interest of patients.

Peer Review reports

Introduction

Diagnosis is the foundation of clinical decision-making, but contemporary problems of over-diagnosis and over-medicalization have confronted this traditional paradigm. In 1878, Charles Peirce proposed a new, pragmatic conception of “meanings”: “Consider what effects, which might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then the whole of our conception of those effects is the whole of our conception of the object” [1].

Applying the pragmatic approach to medical diagnosis, we could say that for a diagnosis to be clinically meaningful, it must have a practical bearing on patient outcomes. Indeed, a recent proposal suggested that diagnosis be replaced by prognosis (or “what is likely to happen”) [2, 3]. This prognostic approach is one step in the pragmatic direction, but it still does not capture all of the practical effects that making a diagnosis has on patients. The impact of prognostic models on patient outcomes, as the impact of making a diagnosis, should also be verified in practice [4]. The effects of making a diagnosis or giving a prognosis on subsequent clinical decisions, treatments, and patient outcomes should be known if we are to practice outcome-based medical care in the best medical interest of patients.

The pragmatic turn is viewed by many as troublesome, for it seems to reverse the traditional diagnosis-therapy-outcomes order of explanation (Fig. 1). In the present paper, we use the story of gestational diabetes to illustrate how a diagnosis can be defined using the clinical outcomes of a pragmatic trial and how pragmatic trials integrated into practice can revolutionize how some pervasive problems of medicine can be addressed. New diagnoses and new diagnostic criteria should be rigorously assessed for their impact on patient outcomes before being widely recommended.

Fig. 1
figure 1

The pragmatic turn. The pragmatic trial approach, to define diagnosis according to clinical outcomes of trials (B) is contrasted with the rationalistic approach (A)

Defining gestational diabetes using prognostic observational studies

Gestational diabetes mellitus (GDM) has been defined as glucose intolerance with onset or first recognition during pregnancy [5]. While the label was first used 50 years ago to identify women at risk of overt diabetes after pregnancy, GDM has been associated with adverse pregnancy outcomes [6,7,8]. Unfortunately, because of this vague definition, the diagnosis of GDM has remained controversial and the lack of consensus has perpetuated widely diverging practices.

The Hyperglycemia and Adverse Pregnancy Outcomes (HAPO) study was conducted between 2000 and 2006 to provide internationally acceptable criteria of GDM; 25,000 pregnant women were observed—untreated (except for pre-defined overt hyperglycemia)—to clarify the risks of adverse outcomes associated with various degrees of maternal glucose intolerance less severe than in overt diabetes [9]. Glucose intolerance was assessed with a one-step 75 g oral glucose tolerance test (OGTT) at 24 to 28 weeks, but clinicians were blinded to results. HAPO showed a linear relationship between maternal glucose levels and four primary outcome measures (birth weight above the 90th percentile for gestational age, primary cesarean delivery, clinical neonatal hypoglycemia, and cord-blood serum C-peptide level above the 90th percentile (an index of fetal hyperinsulinemia)). A linear relationship was also observed for secondary outcomes (preeclampsia, preterm delivery, shoulder dystocia/birth injury, hyperbilirubinemia, and admission to intensive neonatal care). There was no inflexion point or observable threshold.

The International Association of Diabetes and Pregnancy Study Group (IADPSG) thought these new research findings should translate into clinical recommendations. The absence of a threshold called for a decision based on expert opinion: in 2010, they redefined GDM as maternal 75 g-OGTT glucose values corresponding to 1.75 times the odd ratios relative to the mean for selected adverse outcomes [8].

The problem is that ready adoption of the new guidelines was expected to double the number of women diagnosed with GDM. Without rigorous evidence of benefit, the new guidelines could unnecessarily medicalize many pregnancies and re-allocate resources away from high risk women [10, 11]. IADPSG experts argued that a new RCT would be costly, time consuming, and unnecessary, because the efficacy of treatment had already been shown by two previous trials [6, 7]. These trials had studied GDM defined by a 2-step screening method using higher diagnostic thresholds, but it was assumed that treatment efficacy would still apply to women identified by the new definition [8].

Numerous (but not all) national diabetic and healthcare associations around the world adopted the 2010 IADPSG criteria. Many “before/after” studies showed that the new criteria substantially increased the number of GDM cases, but the impact on perinatal outcomes remained controversial [12].

Defining gestational diabetes using the pragmatic trial approach

The controversy centered on two screening methods using different diagnostic cutoffs. The one-step screening approach using HAPO-derived thresholds identified women with mild hyperglycemia as having GDM, but the effects of identifying and treating more women with mild GDM were not known.

In March 2021, Hillier and colleagues reported a randomized study involving nearly 24,000 women [13]. This pragmatic trial integrated into practice compared the two screening methods head-to-head; all women could be included because the need for individual informed consent was waived; recruitment difficulties and bureaucratic hurdles were minimized. The rationale was that both screening approaches were associated with minimal risk and were clinically recommended, and clinicians were uncertain regarding which method to use. The results showed that if twice as many women were diagnosed with GDM with the one-step IADPSG approach (16.5% of all pregnancies) compared to the traditional two-step method (8.5%), there were no significant between-group differences in the risks of the primary outcomes relating to perinatal and maternal complications [13].

Pragmatic lessons from GDM

Our purpose is not to claim that the final word has been established for GDM regarding all health outcomes, for example on long-term outcomes of mothers and their offspring, but rather to examine the wider implications of this story for medical research on diagnosis and care. In our view, the recent pragmatic approach that defined GDM according to all effects on neonatal outcomes, including medical interventions, should have been done instead of the observational HAPO study 20 years ago. We want to examine how pragmatism could change our conceptions.

HAPO studied the “natural history of mild GDM” from an outsider’s perspective, without disturbing normal care except for a simple test, keeping practitioners blinded from results for them not to interfere. This approach is in line with the established research-care separation. If observational studies seem at first glance to be less risky than experimenting using randomized trials during pregnancy, in effect HAPO used participants for the sake of theoretical knowledge, because the blinding strategy assured that women could not gain any benefit from participation. To protect subjects, research ethics committees had to consider whether risks were minimized and whether the “generalizable knowledge” to be gained was worth the risk [14]. But the rationalistic research approach may not be the kind of science that is needed to guide medical care. Observational studies can mislead, because they can only show associations. They cannot predict the effects of interventions (good or bad) on patients. But acting on the new knowledge provided by an observational study is hard to resist. IADPSG experts thought they had a duty to translate observational research findings into clinical guidelines. However, they should not have jumped to conclusions, for clinically pertinent GDM diagnostic criteria should require randomized evidence that to act on new glucose thresholds actually improves pregnancy outcomes in practice. RCTs are admittedly difficult endeavors, time-consuming, and costly, but this is a short-sighted view. Assuming the results of Hillier et al. are definitive, the 20-year controversy and the many-thousand pregnancies that have unnecessarily been flagged and treated since HAPO suggest that nothing is more time consuming or costly than to not do the RCT [15].

Let us examine an alternative scenario. Imagine that Hillier’s trial had shown that adverse pregnancy outcomes were actually prevented by identifying and treating milder cases of GDM. This scenario would mean that blinding the test results at the time of HAPO deprived all participants from receiving the potential benefits. Study designers would claim that this was not known at the time, but that is exactly the problem: in the presence of uncertainty, the interests of research participants are best protected by balancing risks by using randomized allocation [16]. In our view, the evaluation of HAPO by research ethics committees was doubly erroneous: risks for participants were not minimized (the study did not use randomization to balance risks), and the knowledge to be gained was not worth the risk (since observational research findings ran the risk of misleading medical care for decades).

The pragmatic trial approach may not only apply to many other diagnostic problems involving continuous variables (i.e., hypertension). It may also be the best way to verify the value of diagnostic imaging studies in clinical practice. Some diagnostic questions where there are no treatment implications may not need RCT evidence. But when diagnosis or prognosis affects clinical decisions, we believe it is safest to proceed first with a pragmatic trial.

Medical research dedicated to observations, explanations, and the identification of mechanisms is designed to provide reasons to act in practice, but it has long neglected to assess the practical results of these reasons to act on patient outcomes. A pragmatic approach to the design of therapeutic clinical trials was introduced 50 years ago, but only in recent years has it been better understood and promoted [17, 18]. The pragmatic approach may play an equally important role in the definition of meaningful clinical diagnoses. Integrating pragmatic trials into practice can revolutionize medical care in the best interest of patients [19].

Availability of data and materials

NA

References

  1. Peirce CS. How to make our ideas clear. Pop Sci Monthly. 1878;12:286–302.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Croft P, Altman DG, Deeks JJ, Dunn KM, Hay AD, Hemingway H, et al. The science of clinical practice: disease diagnosis or patient prognosis? Evidence about “what is likely to happen” should shape clinical practice. BMC Med. 2015;13(1):20. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-014-0265-4.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  3. Steyerberg EW, Moons KGM, van der Windt DA, Hayden JA, Perel P, Schroter S, et al. Prognosis Research Strategy (PROGRESS) 3: prognostic model research. PLoS Med. 2013;10(2):e1001381. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1001381.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  4. Moons KG, Altman DG, Vergouwe Y, Royston P. Prognosis and prognostic research: application and impact of prognostic models in clinical practice. BMJ. 2009;28(jun04 2):b606. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.b606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. American Diabetes Association. Clinical practice recommendations 2001: gestational diabetes mellitus. Diabetes Care. 2001;24(1):S77–9. https://doi.org/10.2337/diacare.24.1.154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Crowther CA, Hiller JE, Moss JR, McPhee AJ, Jeffries WS, Robinson JS. Effect of treatment of gestational diabetes mellitus on pregnancy outcomes. N Engl J Med. 2005;352(24):2477–86. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa042973.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Landon MB, Spong CY, Thom E, Carpenter MW, Ramin SM, Casey B, et al. A multicenter, randomized trial of treatment for mild gestational diabetes. N Engl J Med. 2009;61(14):1339–48. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa0902430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. International Association of Diabetes and Pregnancy Study Groups Consensus Panel, Metzger BE, Gabbe SG, Persson B, Buchanan TA, Catalano PA, et al. International association of diabetes and pregnancy study groups recommendations on the diagnosis and classification of hyperglycemia in pregnancy. Diabetes Care. 2010;33(3):676–82. https://doi.org/10.2337/dc09-1848.

    Article  CAS  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  9. The HAPO Study Cooperative Research Group. Hyperglycemia and adverse pregnancy outcomes. N Engl J Med. 2008;358(19):1991–2002. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa0707943.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Cheung NW, Moses RG. Gestational diabetes mellitus: is it time to reconsider the diagnostic criteria? Diabetes Care. 2018;41(7):1337–8. https://doi.org/10.2337/dci18-0013.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Long H. Diagnosing gestational diabetes: can expert opinions replace scientific evidence? Diabetologia. 2011;54(9):2211–3. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00125-011-2228-z.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Bilous RW, Jacklin PB, Maresh MJ, Sacks DA. Resolving the gestational diabetes diagnosis conundrum: the need for a randomized controlled trial of treatment. Diabetes Care. 2021;44(4):858–64. https://doi.org/10.2337/dc20-2941.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Hillier TA, Pedula KL, Ogasawara KK, Vesco KK, Oshiro CES, Lubarsky SL, et al. A pragmatic, randomized clinical trial of gestational diabetes screening. N Engl J Med. 2021;384(10):895–904. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa2026028.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  14. Weijer C, Miller PB. When are research risks reasonable in relation to anticipated benefits? Nat Med. 2004;10(6):570–3. https://doi.org/10.1038/nm0604-570.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  15. Casey B. Gestational diabetes - on broadening the diagnosis. N Engl J Med. 2021;384(10):965–6. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMe2100902.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Raymond J, Darsaut TE, Roy D. Care and research concepts should be revised to practice outcome-based medical care. J Clin Epidemiol. 2019;116:155–60. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jclinepi.2019.05.025.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. Schwartz D, Lellouch J. Explanatory and pragmatic attitudes in therapeutical trials. J Clin Epidemiol. 2009;62(5):499–505. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jclinepi.2009.01.012.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  18. Loudon K, Treweek S, Sullivan F, Donnan P, Thorpe KE, Zwarenstein M. The PRECIS-2 tool: designing trials that are fit for purpose. BMJ. 2015;350(may08 1):h2147. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.h2147.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Darsaut TE, Raymond J. Ethical care requires pragmatic care research to guide medical practice under uncertainty. Trials. 2021;22(1):143. https://doi.org/10.1186/s13063-021-05084-.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

NA

Funding

No funding

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

All authors contributed equally to this work. The authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean Raymond.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

NA

Consent for publication

NA

Competing interests

The authors declare they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Raymond, J., Long, H. & Darsaut, T. Pragmatic trials can address diagnostic controversies: recent lessons from gestational diabetes. Trials 23, 246 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1186/s13063-022-06169-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s13063-022-06169-0

Keywords